RECLAIMING ANTHROPOLOGY FOR SCIENCE: A LIBERTARIAN APPROACH Dr Edward Dutton Dr Edward Dutton lectures anthropology at Oulu University in Finland. He studied Theology at Durham University and Anthropology of Religion at Aberdeen University. He is the author of The Finnuit: Finnish Culture and the Religion of Uniqueness (Akademiai Kiado, 2009) and Meeting Jesus at University: Rites of Passage and Student Evangelicals (Ashgate, 2008). He has also written for various newspapers, magazines and journals including the Daily Telegraph, the Guardian, Times Higher Education, Times Educational Supplement, Chronicles, Right Now!, Salisbury Review, Contemporary Review and Quarterly Review. n Allia Scientific Notes No. 17 ISBN 9781856376259 ria ISSN 0267-7067 (Print) ISSN 2040-5774 (Online)
For Life, Liberty, and Property 2010: Libertarian Alliance & Edward Dutton The views expressed in this publication are those of rta the author and not necessarily those of the Libertarian Alliance, its Committee, its Advisory Council or its subscribers. Dr Chris R. Tame (1949-2006): Founder Dr Tim Evans: President 2 Lansdowne Row Dr Sean Gabb: Director David Farrer: Scottish Director & Financial Director David Davis: Blogmaster & Scientific Adviser Dr Nigel Gervas Meek: Publications Director Libe Mario Huet: LA Forum Listmaster Telephone: 0870 242 1712 Christian Michel: European Director Email: [email protected] David Carr: Legal Affairs Spokesman Website: www.libertarian.co.uk Patrick Crozier: Transport Spokesman LI BERTARI AN AL LI ANCE RECLAIMING ANTHROPOLOGY FOR SCIENCE: A LIBERTARIAN APPROACH Dr Edward Dutton Abstract
1920s it was becoming accepted that anthropologists
should engage in fieldwork (‘participant observation’) and
Scientific anthropologists tend to argue for the veracity of
so produce ‘ethnographies’ (see Gellner 1995, Ch. 1). But
their approach and assume that the most logical approach
it has moved away from its scientific origins. From the
will ultimately reclaim the discipline from postmodernists
1920s, scholars such as Margaret Mead (1928) began to
and extreme-naturalists. This article advocates scientific
argue that all cultures are equal, can only be understood
anthropology but stresses that being logically coherent is
through their own terms (cultural relativism), there is al-
only part of the process of scientific revolutions. It dem-
most no hereditary influence on personality (cultural de-
onstrates that anthropology is broadly in the grip of those
terminism) and so the anthropologist’s duty is to describe
who are implicitly religious—not rational—and then pre-
and preserve the culture. Cultural determinism was pulled
sents a libertarian manifesto on how anthropology—in
apart by Derek Freeman’s (1983) refutation of Mead’s
practical terms—might be returned to the scientific fold.
shoddy research in Western Samoa, which purported to
show a ‘negative instance’ in terms of teenage angst. This
shattering of anthropological orthodoxy—by a ‘scientific’
Introduction
outsider—plunged anthropology into crisis but, even by
1983, Mead’s form of anthropology was being criticised
The aim of this research report is to look at how scientists
from the postmodern perspective as well.
might begin to reclaim social anthropology from the anti-
positivist and especially the postmodern tradition which
Accordingly, there has developed a divide in social anthro-
has risen to some prominence within it. The article is, I
pology between those who believe that social anthropol-
fully concede, a series of suggestions and possibilities but
ogy should be ultimately underpinned by science—and so
I think that advancing such possibilities is useful in set-
evolution—and the ‘naturalists’, who do not. American
ting-off what I see as an important debate abut anthropol-
anthropologist Lawrence Kuznar (1997, 176) argues that
ogy’s future. The arguments advanced are suggestions but
the discipline of social anthropology—even more so than
they are justified because they attempt to answer a signifi-
other social sciences—has been drawn away from science
cant question asked—but as yet not satisfactorily an-
and towards being a form of replacement religiosity.
swered—by scientific anthropologists. Persuaded of the
‘Anthropology must be seen to be thoroughly rent at this
veracity of scientific anthropology, ‘Where do we go from
point,’ he laments, ‘with its own practitioners deconstruct-
ing it in an intellectual civil war which threatens to balkan-
ize, if not totally destroy, the discipline forever . . . Scien-
Accordingly, this article is an exercise in practical philoso-
tific anthropologists seem holed-up in defensive citadels
phy. Based on the premises that anthropology should be
while postmodern and critical factions have taken the field
scientific—as we will discuss—in order to meaningfully
and are beginning to snipe at one another’ (211).
assist in developing more nuanced theories of human na-
ture and that it is potentially useful in this regard, and,
In his book, Reclaiming a Scientific Anthropology (Kuznar
moreover, the premise that civilization is required for sci-
1997), he provides ample evidence for this summary. A
ence to flourish (see Popper 1966a/b, 1963, Sandall 2001),
‘crisis of representation’ began, in social anthropology in
what practical action should be taken to return anthropol-
around the 1970s in which all of anthropology’s funda-
mental assumptions came to be questioned and some have
insisted that anthropology remains in this state of crisis
(e.g. Rees 2010a). Hymes (1974) criticised anthropologists
Anthropology and Science
for imposing ‘Western categories’—such as Western
measurement—on those they study, arguing that this was
Physical anthropology is the study of the evolutionary
a form of domination. Asad (1973) criticised field-work
origins of humans. To a great extent, this remains a sci-
based anthropology for ultimately being indebted to colo-
ence. Social—or cultural—anthropology grew out of
nialism and it has been argued (e.g. Sandall 2001) that this
physical anthropology in the nineteenth century. Begin-
has led some anthropologists to focussing on their own
ning with tribes or folk life, it attempted to record and to
psychologies, and their fallibility as scientific instruments,
scientifically understand what are commonly called
more than their observations. Andreski (1974, 109) might
‘cultures’, often underpinned by a belief in at least partial
counter that this reflects ‘methodological perfectionism’ as
biological determinism. This discipline began by drawing
does the essentialist1 demand that anthropological con-
upon sources—‘armchair anthropology’—but by the
cepts be dissected in detail to the neglect of actual analy-
LI BERTARI AN AL LI ANCE
sis.2 The instruments of physical science are also fallible
a void of Nothing where we can understand nothing. It is
as is a zoologist in relation to that which he observes.
epistemologically pessimistic. And as Bruce (2002) argues
Others drew upon the postmodern deconstruction of
it makes many ideological assumptions; for example that
texts to argue that anthropology was ultimately composed
all cultures are equal or that colonialism is inherently
of ‘texts’—ethnographies—which can be deconstructed
(e.g. Marcus and Cushman 1982). By extension, as all
texts—including scientific texts—could be deconstructed,
Edward Wilson (1998) argues, in my view persuasively, for
some anthropologists began to accept that reality itself
Consilience of the various academic disciplines. In sum-
was tenuous and only ‘within the text.’ Indeed, for an-
mary, he maintains that knowledge is reached both by
thropologists such as Wagner (1981) there is, in effect, no
fragmentation—in the sense of reductionism in order to
objective truth. All attempts at constructing reality are
gain purchase on an object of study—but also, crucially,
subjective responses to the ‘culture shock’ caused by the
by reconstruction. We are witnessing an ‘ongoing frag-
cultural ‘other.’ Watson (1991, 79) is explicit that there is
mentation of knowledge’ (8) as we divide into innumer-
no objective reality. Anthropological accounts are
able subdisciplines and ‘consilence’ would consequently
be positive for scholarship. Consilence is metaphysical
but the ‘success’ of science provides a strong case for its
Other scholars have pursued postmodern deconstruction
veracity and, indeed, Kuznar (1997, Ch. 3) gives examples
by questioning anthropological categories. For example,
of the proven success of scientific anthropology above its
Rees (2010a) is sceptical of ‘culture’ because it has a start-
ing point in history, plays down nuance, is static, and im-
poses a Western category on the other . . . but this is, of
Wilson (1998) notes that ethics, social policy, environ-
course, true of all categories of apprehension. In the
mental policy and social science are clearly closely related
nominalist tradition, they are to be used cautiously if they
domains yet they stand apart with separate practitioners,
are helpful (see Dennett 1995, 95) and to term such cate-
modes of analysis, language and standards. The result is
gories ‘reified’ or ‘essentialist’ is really a straw-man argu-
confusion with regard to the areas of overlap yet it is here
ment. Equally to suggest that the changes since the 1980s
‘where most real world problems exist’ (10). Wilson
have been so radical that culture is no longer useful fails
therefore argues that these specialists must, and can, reach
to understand the broad anthropological definition of the
an agreement on standards of abstract principles and evi-
word and that, for a nominalist, words can be malleable
dentiary proof. He then proceeds to prove how humanity
and employed as and when useful. Some argue that
and social science explanations are ultimately question-
‘representation’ and ‘theory’ are problematic (e.g. Rees
begging (and, in some cases, simply ideological) and fully
2010a) but fail to appreciate that any description is inher-
make sense only with ‘consilience’ into biology and psy-
ently an act of representing and even language is under-
chology. Wilson’s idea has been criticised with critics cit-
pinned by some kind of theory (see Gentner 1982). They
ing a belief that a ‘rational society’ is not the same as a
may counter that understanding arrives ex nihilo, in the
‘scientific society’ but it has been countered that these
break-down of fieldwork, but this seems closer to reli-
critics then use ‘science’ as their ultimate model for a ra-
gious understanding than scientific (see Wiebe 1999).
tional society. Wilson has also been criticised for an idio-
And Denis Dutton (1999) observes that other social scien-
syncratic view of ‘the Enlightenment quest’ but this does
tists reflect postmodern influence with scholarship that
not undermine the logic of consilience (Segerstråle 2000,
says very little but is verbose and makes use of intellec-
tual-sounding jargon such as, in anthropology, ‘reified,’
‘emergent,’ ‘problematised,’ ‘discontinuities’, ‘agency’ and
Consilience characterizes scientific enquiry. It must be
so on3 as well as fallacious arguments, such as that
possible to reduce research in a particular discipline down
‘culture’ should be dismissed because it is old-fashioned or
to the discipline which ultimately underpins it. This is an
important sign that a discipline is scientific. ‘Science’ must
also involve certain agreed characteristics. Lawrence
The problems with postmodern anthropology are fairly
Kuznar (1997, 22) argues that these are the following:
clear as Gellner (1992) observes. Its cultural relativism is
1) It must be solely empirical. If a discipline is based on
hypocritical, best summarised by Richard Dawkins (2003,
unprovable or inconsistent dogmas it is not scientific
15) with the lines: ‘Show me a cultural relativist at 3000
and if it places something—such as ‘empathy for in-
feet and I’ll show you a hypocrite . . . If you are flying to
formants’—above the pursuit of truth it is not sci-
an international conference of anthropologists . . . the
reason you will probably get there, the reason you won’t
2) It must be systematic and exploratory.
plummet into the ploughed field is that a lot of Western,
3) It must be logical. This means, in particular, that fal-
scientifically trained engineers have got their sums right.’
lacious arguments, such as appeal ad hominem, ap-
It is also inconsistent because it attempts to use the logic
peal to motive or any other form of rhetoric must be
of Western science to question the usefulness of logical
avoided. It also means that the research and argu-
reasoning itself. Its extreme essentialism—in radically
deconstructing categories of apprehension—leads us to a
4) It must be theoretical, it must attempt to explain, to
situation where we cannot begin to understand anything
answer questions and, where possible, predict. In this
so postmodernism, as Scruton (2000) puts it, takes us into
regard, it engages in nominalism and only cautious
LI BERTARI AN AL LI ANCE
Goldstone 1980), whereby anthropology is brought back
5) It must be self-critical, prepared to abandon long-held
into the scientific-fold. What can be done to hasten it in
6) Its propositions must be open to testing and falsifica-
7) As it wishes to be falsified and as anybody can, in
How to Create a Revolution
theory, do so; science should be a public activity.
8) It should assume that reality is actually real and can be
Italian revolutionary Antonio Gramsci diverged from
understood; it should be epistemologically optimistic.
Marx’s view that only if revolutionaries take hold of the
Accordingly, it must accept that there is an objectively
means of production and distribution can they take power
correct understanding of how the world works which
from the ruling class and thence take their place. Instead,
the ‘ruling class’ posit a ‘hegemonic’ ideology which
‘legitimises’ their position. They then impose this ideol-
Rees (2010b, 900) has defined science as ‘thoughtful, sin-
ogy on the populace through their control of the
cere research’ but this is so broad that it would not distin-
‘ideological state apparatus’—legal and political admini-
guish science from art.4 If we accept Kuznar’s model of
stration, schools, universities, churches, the media, the
science and that anthropology, to be logically coherent,
family and the underlying assumptions of popular culture
must be part of it then it is reasonable to ask ‘Where do
(Giddens 1997, 583). In general, the revolutionary wants
we go from here?’ and this is how Kuznar (1997, 11) ends
to bring about ‘manufactured consent’ (Gramsci 1971,
215). The revolution has been truly successful when the
ideology ceases to be controversial but, instead, becomes
regarded as common sense, as something that no reason-
Religion, Science and Paradigms
able person would question. In such a situation, counter-
revolutionaries do not—usually—need to be actively per-
Kuznar accepts that social anthropology has become
secuted by the state. Most citizens will regard them as at
dominated by what he terms the latter-day ‘religious’—
best laughable and at worst dangerous and treat them ac-
those who fervently hold to inconsistent, illogical views,
what Bailey (1997) terms the ‘implicitly religious’. Despite
the veracity of scientific anthropology, it has been pushed
So, can such a theory be applied to ‘anthropology’? With
to the sidelines and, indeed, Kuznar observes that Kuhn’s
many nuances, I would argue it could be. Anthropology
(1963) model of scientific revolutions accepts that being
(and many disciplines) is rendered far more complicated
scientifically correct is only part of a successful scientific
than a nation-state because it is increasingly international
revolution. Once a new paradigm is widely accepted, a
and beyond the control of individual nation states which
form of tribalism will rear its head and there will be a reac-
are, in turn, influenced by transnational forces (e.g. Becher
tionary and irrational response—by those who have built
and Trowler 2001). The ideological ‘apparatus’ takes the
their careers on the new paradigm – to those who attempt
form of peer-reviewed journals and books, conferences,
to logically challenge it, as observed in the reaction to
anthropology societies and anthropology departments. In
Derek Freeman’s (1983, 1999) critique of Margaret Mead
addition, the broader non-academic media is an important
(1928) (see Freeman 1996). Andreski (1974) and many
piece of the apparatus. The way in which this apparatus
others (e.g. Jenkins 2009) have observed the parallels be-
works, in terms of power-dynamics, has been discussed,
tween scientific practice and religion. Andeski (1974, 249)
more broadly, by a number of scholars (see, for example,
argues that scientists should be ‘iconoclastic’—relentlessly
Andreski 1974, Martin 1999 or Welch 2009) and I will
tearing down that which is widely accepted in pursuit of
the truth. But iconoclastic scientists soon gain a cult-like
following of scientists who wish to preserve the new
Anthropologists can influence whether or not dissenting
status quo, ironically rejecting the very kind of iconoclastic
anthropology is published through the kind of peer-
scientist whom they have originally followed.
reviews which they write for journals or publishers. As
rhetoric-expert John Welch (2009) puts it, ‘Blind peer re-
Kuznar makes various suggestions on what should be
view can also be a way to abuse privilege. Someone with a
done but this involves little more than repeating that an-
score to settle can do so by using the blind review process
thropology should be scientific. This may persuade think-
punitively.’ Or, if they are journal editors, influence is
ing, critical anthropologists who have only ever been ex-
wielded through the ability to decide whether an article is
posed to naturalist or postmodern anthropology. Kuznar
peer-reviewed at all or whether, sometimes, to over-rule
may have rescued anthropology intellectually but he is not
the reviews and this may even done for financial reasons.
being practical. Anthropology’s takeover by cultural rela-
As Welch (2009) suggests, ‘Malaria is more abundant to-
tivists was a kind of revolution. If Kuhn is right, it may
day than it ever was, yet medical journals are more likely
take a counter-revolution to return it to science. And if
to publish works about Cialis or whatever other big-
Kuznar (1997, 211) is correct then social anthropology is
money drug funds the ads that keep that journal afloat.’
in a state of crisis induced by the postmodern critique.
This ‘crisis’ is, as is widely acknowledged, the most auspi-
If they are asked to write books reviews, these can be used
cious circumstance for a revolution (see Kuhn 1963,
as attempts to smear and sink a book with which they
LI BERTARI AN AL LI ANCE
disagree for ideological reasons. Equally, conference or-
implicitly religious nature of postmodern and cultural rela-
ganisers can control what kinds of papers are given at a
tivist anthropology, thus inculcating the next generation
conference. Scholars will be nominated as reviewers, or
with scientific anthropology. Equally, anthropologists
editors, because of previous publishing success in journals
could use their influence in departments to strongly argue
and books and, indeed, academic positions which they
against the appointment of potential colleagues who seem
hold, though they were may review papers only tangen-
to advocate anti-scientific anthropology and employ their
tially related to their area. They will in turn be appointed
influence as reviewers to prevent the publication of anti-
to these positions because of their publishing success and
scientific anthropology literature and highlight the flaws of
will, if they ascend the academic ladder, be able to control
that which is published in letters to the editor, critical
who else works in their department, perhaps on ideologi-
book reviews (specifically requesting to review books by
cal grounds if they wish. In turn, they will be more likely
postmodern anthropologists) and even articles for the
to be published by academic publishers if they have pub-
lished in the right journals, hold an academic position and,
especially in the case of a PhD thesis, been funded by a
There are many possibilities for provocative articles in the
prestigious funding body where funding distribution can
press which could damage postmodern anthropology.
itself be politically manipulated as can the process of the
For example, all practicing anthropologists—or members
‘PhD Defence’ or viva voce. The distribution of funding is
of anthropological societies—could be invited to a sign a
another piece of apparatus which can make or break re-
document from which no genuine scientist could possibly
demure; stating that they accept scientific principles. Fail-
ure to do so would then be publicly highlighted which
Finally, a scholar is far more likely to be of interest to the
would likely be damaging to the reputations of the schol-
media if he has published academic books and articles and
ars in question and their departments. There may be phi-
holds an academic position or higher qualification, be-
losophical objections to science but these are no more
cause these provide him with authority rendering any con-
matters for anthropologists then they are for chemists if,
troversial statements he might make far more newswor-
indeed, social anthropology is genuinely a science. In the
thy. Media coverage will, in turn, affect his academic
Sokal Hoax (see Sokal and Bricmont 1998) American
physicist Alan Sokal sent a lampoon of postmodern writ-
ing (Sokal 1996) to a postmodern cultural studies journal
As Andreski (1974, Ch. 1) argues, a power structure is by
as a test to see whether they would publish it, which they
its very nature conservative. It is controlled by the domi-
duly did. Similar lampoons could be sent to leading an-
nant ideology and established academics and any challenge
thropology journals. I suspect—and hope—that many
to this ideology, or the system involved, is likely to be a
would be rejected but some might not be and, if this oc-
challenge to the life’s work, social position and even salary
curred, media attention could be brought to this which
of those in control, a point which Westbrook (2008)
would accordingly pressure the journals and highlight the
makes about postmodern anthropology. Accordingly, as
Andreski (1974, 49) notes, the challenge may come from
daring small publishers, less prestigious journals, scholars
outside the discipline, popular academic writing and even
The Need for a Libertarian Society
from publishers and scholars in academically peripheral
But I would submit that the influence of postmodernism
in anthropology is ultimately a reflection of the nature of
Of course, in practice some pieces of the apparatus are far
the society in which the apparatus operate. Andreski
more important than others. It is reviewers, writers and
(1974) observes that the dominant discourse in social sci-
editors of the leading journals—and for the leading pub-
ences tends to be the dominant discourse in society at
lishers and the most prestigious funding bodies—who
large. Though social science may influence society, in
have the real power over the most important parts of the
general it reflects the dominant ideology to a far greater
apparatus. Perhaps it is not unreasonable to argue that
extent than physical science because it is more difficult for
the real centres of power are journals published in the
physical sciences—with their greater degree of empirical
USA and Britain and especially American Anthropologist,
rigour—to be hijacked by the implicitly religious. More-
Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute and related jour-
over, Gellner (1996, Ch. 1) notes that the various anthro-
nals. The most significant publishers might include Ox-
pological disciplines have been founded on implicitly reli-
ford University Press and Harvard University Press and
gious ideas. Nineteenth century Western anthropology
these might also be amongst the most important depart-
drew upon the ‘Great Chain of Being’ to assert a racial
and even religious hierarchy whereby the Northern Euro-
pean was, in every way, superior. It was dominated by
A counter-revolution involves advocates of scientific an-
biological determinism, something which developed into a
thropology taking hold of these organs of influence by
dogma. Eastern anthropology developed in the context of
effective use of the influence they already have. Scientific
small-nation nationalism, assuming that its purpose was to
anthropologists should insist on teaching their under-
build a nation—accepting many elements of Romantic
graduates—as part of their courses—about the philoso-
nationalism—and so preserve and document its folk cul-
phy of science and be quite explicit with them about the
LI BERTARI AN AL LI ANCE
Accordingly, postmodern anthropology is part of a
ernment and Politics Department . . . Doubtless,
broader cultural revolution where the apparatus of
many students will be upset to lose their chance of
power—including politically significant university depart-
getting a degree . . . bearing in mind the mixture of
ments that relate to how we treat and understand peo-
worthless knowledge and ruling class indoctrination
ple—has been taken over by those in the Gramscian tradi-
from which we would be saving them, they would not
tion. As such, scientific anthropologists should campaign,
suffer on balance’ (Gabb 2007, 58).
in all countries, for the form of government most condu-
cive to science and I would submit that this would be one
I would counter that lawyers are necessary in a society
without a clear and lauded ‘ideology’ and so not a govern-
governed by the Rule of Law and this is the form of soci-
ment in the implicitly religious Romantic traditions of
ety which Gabb wants as opposed to totalitarian society
socialism or nationalism (see Scruton 2000) let alone ex-
where the law is enforced unfairly. Also, all the depart-
plicit religion. This may be a form of moderate, libertar-
ments he lists can make a contribution to civilization as
ian conservatism and Kuznar (1997, 22) observes that
long as they are scientific and this is why I suggest that
science, by its very nature, is libertarian. Nevertheless, a
funding should be withdrawn on a case-by-case basis in
government of this kind – motivated by a desire for free-
the manner which I have advocated, though as Gabb is
dom—would not only defend the interests of science but
suggesting action to avoid a counter-revolution perhaps
would realise that postmodernists, cultural relativists and
such departments could be initially relieved of funding
the like were ultimately a manifestation of the power of
and the issue reassessed in less pressing times. If universi-
the opposition, of the displaced ‘ruling class.’ Intelligent
ties were to receive no government-funding, then social
lobbying would, therefore, be far more likely to persuade
science departments would be beholden to the interests of
such a government that direct or indirect government-
benevolent donors. I would argue that this would only
funding for research should be based on the degree to
make them as corruptible as if they were beholden to the
which the research is actually scientific. Academics could
interests of the government of the day. This is a problem,
be made to justify their research—according to the criteria
of course, but it must be understood in the context of the
outlined—and if it were not scientific (or broadly so by
benefits to science of a relatively libertarian government.
contributing to a civilization conducive to scientific prac-
It might be argued that if all government funding were
tice)6 funding would be cut from the scholar and from the
withdrawn from universities then scientific research would
department until it would be financially very difficult to
likely gain funding from industry and the medical profes-
sion, paid for by the public, and so would continue.
There would always be a need for lawyers—so the Law
Moreover, any justification would have to include a sum-
would gain funding from the public and could be self-
mary—written in clear language—making clear the useful-
sustaining. Such a situation might also see substantial
ness of the research for an academic in an entirely differ-
cutbacks in higher education and a rise in ‘independent
ent area of study. Evidence of verbosity and jargon
scholars,’ especially in history, philosophy and so on,
would, accordingly, be extremely costly.
whose research could not be corrupted by the desire for
Libertarian philosopher Sean Gabb (2007) goes further in
a broader manifesto on how to win back England from
And, of course, once anthropology is returned to science a
postmodernists. He delineates in detail how to destroy—
counter-revolution must be prevented. Welch (2009) ar-
at great speed—what he sees as the semi-totalitarian state
gues for radical reform of the peer-review process such
which has been constructed in England since World War
that scholarship is published online and continuously up-
II and especially under the New Labour Government of
dated as it is constantly peer-reviewed. The form of peer-
1997 to 2010. In terms of holding society together, he
review which is widely practiced, he argues, is slow, easily
also implicitly argues in favour of some limited form of
corruptible, reliant on a degree of good luck, most jour-
ethnicity-based identity (54).7 I would argue that his
nals and publishers who employ it inherently restrict ac-
methods—such as abolishing almost all restrictions on
cess to science (through expensive, jargon-filled publica-
free speech and association, guaranteeing these as unas-
tions which few people read); it is essentially a form of
sailable rights and abolishing and destroying all the re-
vanity publishing. Replacing this kind of peer-review un-
cords of most government departments and commissions
dermines the power-base of established scholars but it
and generally making government insignificantly small by
could only be done once the ‘revolution’ had occurred.
privatising almost everything—would aid such a revolu-
Prior to scientists taking control of anthropology’s major
tion. However, I would nuance his attitude to education.
journals, scholars would be unlikely to follow Welch’s idea
He argues that once a libertarian government is elected—
fearing their publications would lack impact and prestige.
assuming it can be elected—all government funding
As in my own case, they may also fear that they will not be
read by other scholars and so fail to contribute to the de-
bate or receive feedback allowing their ideas to be cri-
‘. . . we should cut off all state-funding to the univer-
tiqued and further developed. Accordingly, to introduce
sities. We might allow some separate, transitional
such an idea anthropologists would have to take over and
support for a few science departments. But we should be careful not to allow another penny of sup-port for an Economics or Law or Sociology or Gov-LI BERTARI AN AL LI ANCE
But the problem is that—for the scheme to work—there
But, of course, it is tentative and I would welcome the
would have to be some degree of ‘authority’ involved,
suggestions of other scientific anthropologists on how it
such as that potential reviewers have PhDs (the provision
might be developed. Perhaps one of the obvious prob-
of which is corruptible) or books published and that those
lems is whether such action is in the spirit of caution and
that run the new system be respected experts. And schol-
self-criticism which underpins critical rationalism. Can
ars will desire a way to sift through all the dross and aca-
scientists be sufficiently ‘sure’ to ‘act’ in such a decisive
demic books and journals provide such a means, if not a
perfect means, of doing this. They gain prestige by virtue
of the calibre and influence of the people published in or
by them and the extent and nature of their readership.
Perhaps this can be achieved by an initial insistence that
any submitted article, no matter how bad, is anonymously
(1) For Essentialists it is the task of science to describe the
reviewed in the traditional fashion by two or three recog-
true nature of things and thus focus on the definitions of
nised scholars, the suggestions at least responded to,8 re-
terms. Nominalists are more interested in understanding
reviewed and further responded to before publication
how something behaves in different circumstances and
which then occurs even if the reviews are broadly nega-
they make use of a concept if it is helpful.
tive. Once published, all scholars are invited to read it and
(2) As we will see below, this can be a useful means of
anonymously send reviews continuously. Following
suppressing dissident research. A peer-reviewer can sim-
Welch’s vision, it might be difficult to find the best schol-
ply insist that a category that has been criticised by post-
arship other than through a system whereby it was ‘liked’
modernists (such as ‘culture’) must be ‘problematised’ in
or cited by eminent scholars, which would not be that
so much depth that there is no space—in the word limit
dissimilar to what occurs now. However, the system
of an article—to engage in actual analysis, forcing the
would make it far more difficult to abuse peer-review (by
scholar to either give-up on the article or the category
using it to prevent publication for ideological reasons) and
would render a counter-revolution far more difficult.
(3) Interview with Denis Dutton (2010) with reference to
(4) This is a rejoinder to Dutton (2010).
More than just ‘good luck’
(5) For example, Gellner was a philosopher before turning
to anthropology. Malinowski and Andreski were both
Kuznar (1997, 224) ends his defence of scientific anthro-
from Poland but challenged British anthropology and so-
pology thus: ‘Anthropology should centre and orchestrate
around a principle theme, the quest for understanding the
(6) For a discussion of the necessity of civilization to sci-
human condition using scientific principles, yet be tolerant
of the discordance that will, in the end, make it rich and
(7) A number of scholars (e.g. Salter 2006) have argued
meaningful. I wish the best of luck to us all.’ I partly
that some kind of hallowed worldview is required to hold
agree with Kuznar and admire his positive attitude and
civilization together in the face of those who would bring
magnanimousness. But he also seems to reflect the kind
it down and the idea of a genetic extended family, and
of implicit religiosity which I have highlighted. Tolerating
passing on one’s genes, is a prime motivator in any animal
‘discordance’ (by which he means postmodern anthropol-
including humans. This form, in effect, of ancestor-
ogy, creation science and other shoddy research) may ‘in
worship avoids stifling intellectual dissent—as in when
the end, make it rich and meaningful’—in that it forces
society is held together with dogmas (see Benoist 2004)—
scientists to be more self-aware and hone the expression
but I appreciate there are difficulties with it.
of their arguments—but it may sink anthropology and
(8) Of course, there is room for corruption here because
science more broadly because some postmoderns are
the editor could insist that they have not responded even
openly opposed to science. So Kuznar’s assertion smacks
if they have so strict guidelines on what constitutes a
of bien pensant prophecy. And while anthropologists may
‘response’ would have to be drawn up and mutually ac-
need auspicious coincidences, wishing us ‘the best of luck’
doesn’t really help unless you believe in the genuine power
Bibliography
It may help in that it makes Kuznar and, perhaps by ex-
tension, other scientific anthropologists seem like very
Andreski, Stanislav, (1974), Social Sciences as Sorcery, Lon-
nice people and this, in turn, may make others more in-
clined to support them. I’m sure Lawrence Kuznar is a
Asad, Talal, (1973), ‘Introduction’ in Talal Asad, (ed.),
very nice man and his book shows him to be an extremely
Anthropology and the Colonial Encounter, Atlantic
thoughtful one. But though being nice may help, I would
suggest that the—albeit tentative and brief—manifesto I
Bailey, Edward, (1997), Implicit Religion in Contemporary Soci-
have suggested may help as well in ensuring that anthro-
pology returns to a quest to understand the human condi-
Barth, Frederik, (2002), ‘Towards a Richer Description of
tion and human nature through scientific means.
Analysis of Cultural Phenomena’ in Fox, Richard
and King, Barbara, (eds), Anthropology Beyond Cul-LI BERTARI AN AL LI ANCE search in Social Problems and Public Policy, Stamford:
Becher, Tony and Trowler, Paul, (2001), Academic Tribes and Territories: Intel ectual Enquiry and the Culture of
Mead, Margaret, (1928), Coming of Age in Samoa: A Psycho-Disciplines, Buckingham: Open University Press.
logical Study of Primitive Youth for Western Civilization,
Benoist, Alain de, (2004), On Being a Pagan, Atlanta: Ultra
Popper, Karl, (1966a), The Open Society and its Enemies I: The
Bruce, Steve, (2002), God is Dead: Secularization in the West,
Spell of Plato, London: Routledge, Kegan and Paul.
Popper, Karl, (1966b), The Open Society and its Enemies II:
Dawkins, Richard, (2003), A Devil’s Chaplain: Reflections on The High Tide of Prophecy: Hegel, Marx and the After-Hope, Lies, Science and Love, New York: Basic Books.
math, London: Routledge, Kegan and Paul.
Dennett, Daniel, (1995), Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution
Popper, Karl, (1963), Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth and the Meaning of Life, New York: Simon and
of Scientific Knowledge, London: Routledge, Kegan
Dutton, Denis. Interview with Author. August 2010.
Rasmussen, Susan, (2008), ‘The people of solitude: recall-
Dutton, Denis, (5th February 1999), ‘Language Crimes: A
ing and reinventing essuf (the wild) in traditional
Lesson in How Not to Write Courtesy of the Pro-
and emergent Tuareg cultural spaces’ in Journal of
fessoriate,’ in the Wal Street Journal.
the Royal Anthropological Institute, 14: 3.
Dutton, Edward, (2010), ‘Towards a Scientific Anthropol-
Rees, Tobias, (2010a), ‘To open up new spaces of
ogy’ in Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute, 16:
thought: anthropology BSC (beyond society and
culture)’ in Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute,
Freeman, Derek, (1999), The Fateful Hoaxing of Margaret Mead: A Historical Analysis of her Samoan Research,
Rees, Tobias, (2010b), ‘On the challenge—and the
beauty—of contemporary anthropological enquiry:
Freeman, Derek, (1996), ‘Derek Freeman: Reflections of a
a response to Edward Dutton’ in Journal of the Royal
Heretic’ in The Evolutionist, http://www.lse.ac.uk/
Anthropological Institute, 16: 4.
collections/darwin/evolutionist/freeman.htm
Sandall, Roger, (2001), The Culture Cult: On Designer Tribal-
Freeman, Derek, (1983), Margaret Mead and Samoa: The ism and Other Essays, Oxford: Westview Press.
Making and Unmaking of an Anthropological Myth, Har-
Salter, Frank, (2006), On Genetic Interests: Family, Ethnicity and Humanity in an Age of Mass Migration, New
Gabb, Sean, (2007), Culture Revolution, Culture War: How the Conservatives Lost England and How to Get it Back,
Scruton, Roger, (2000), Modern Culture, London: Contin-
Gellner, Ernest, (1995), Anthropology and Politics: Revolutions
Segerstråle, Ullica, (2000), Defenders of the Truth: The Sociobi-in the Sacred Grove, Oxford: Blackwell.
ology Debate, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gellner, Ernest, (1992), Post-Modernism, Reason and Religion,
Sokal, Alan, (1996), ‘Transgressing the Boundaries: To-
wards a Transformative Hermeneutics of Quantum
Gentner, Dedre, (1982), ‘Are Scientific Analogies Meta-
Gravity’ in Social Text, 217-252.
phors?’ in Miall, David, (ed.), Metaphor: Problems and
Sokal, Alan, and Bricmont, Jean, (1998), Fashionable Non-Perspectives, Brighton: Harvester Press.
sense: Postmodern Intel ectuals’ Abuse of Science, New
Giddens, Anthony, (1997), Sociology, Cambridge: Polity
Wagner, Roy, (1981), The Invention of Culture, Chicago: Uni-
Goldstone, Jack, (1980), ‘Theories of Revolutions: The
Third Generation’ in World Politics, 32.
Watson, Graham, (1991), ‘Rewriting Culture’ in Richard
Gramsci, Antonio, (1971), Selections From Prison Notebooks,
Fox, (ed.), Recapturing Anthropology: Working in the Present, Santa Fe: School of American Research.
Hymes, Dell, (1974), ‘The Use of Anthropology: Critical,
Welch, John, (2009), Academic Evolution, http://
Political, Personal’ in Dell Hymes, (ed.), Reinventing Anthropology, New York: Vintage Books.
Jenkins, Timothy, (2009), ‘Faith and the Scientific Mind/
Westbrook, David, (2008), Navigators of the Contempory: Why
Faith in the Scientific Mind: The Implicit Religion
Ethnography Matters, Chicago: Chicago University
of Science in Contemporary Britain’ in Implicit Relig-
Wiebe, Donald, (1999), ‘Does understanding religion re-
Kuhn, Thomas, (1963), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions,
quire a religious understanding?’ in McCutcheon,
Russell T., (ed.), The Insider/Outsider Problem in the
Kuznar, Lawrence, (1997), Reclaiming a Scientific Anthropol-Study of Religion: A Reader, New York: Cassell.
ogy, Walnut Creek: AltaMira Press.
Wilson, Edward O., (1998), Consilience: Towards the Unity of
Marcus, George and Cushman, Dick, (1974),
Knowledge, New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
‘Ethnographies as Texts’ in Annual Review of Anthro-
Martin, Brian, (1999), ‘Suppression of Dissent in Science’
in William Frudenberg and Ted Young, (eds), Re-
Illinois Rainbow Leadership Camp Health Form ALLERGIES (please include child’s reactions) Meds_____Food_____Contact_____Latex_____ Name ____________________________________ List:_____________________________________ _________________________________________ Birth date_________________________________ _________________________________________ Parent/Guardian___________________________
Mediating Conflicts of Need, Greed, and CreedWhilecivilwarsareoftenseenastheproductofunfulfilledbasicneeds, internal ethnic conflicts are commonly driven by privategain and collective beliefs as well. Such combinations of motives—mixing need, greed, and creed—pose especially complex challenges formediators and underscore the importance of prevention over cure.1 For oncethe three combine to